Modern Stochastics: Theory and Applications logo


  • Help
Login Register

  1. Home
  2. Issues
  3. Volume 1, Issue 1 (2014)
  4. The consistent criteria of hypotheses

Modern Stochastics: Theory and Applications

Submit your article Information Become a Peer-reviewer
  • Article info
  • Full article
  • More
    Article info Full article

The consistent criteria of hypotheses
Volume 1, Issue 1 (2014), pp. 3–11
L. Aleksidze   M. Mumladze   Z. Zerakidze  

Authors

 
Placeholder
https://doi.org/10.15559/vmsta-2014.1.1.5
Pub. online: 27 June 2014      Type: Research Article      Open accessOpen Access

Received
30 January 2013
Revised
4 March 2014
Accepted
5 June 2014
Published
27 June 2014

Abstract

In this paper we define the consistent criteria of hypotheses such as the probability of any kind of errors is zero for given criteria. We prove necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of such criteria.

1 Basic notions and consistent criterion on hypothesis for countable family of probability measures

Let $(E,S)$ be a measurable space with a given family of probability measures: $\{\mu _{i},i\in I\}$.
Definition 1.
The family $\{\mu _{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in I\}$ of probability measures is called orthogonal (singular) if $\mu _{i}$ and $\mu _{j}$ are orthogonal for each $i\ne j$.
Definition 2.
The family $\{\mu _{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in I\}$ of probability measures is called separable if there exists a family of S-measurable sets $\{X_{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in I\}$ such that the relations are fulfilled:
  • (1) $\forall i\in I$ $\forall j\in I$ $\mu _{i}(X_{j})=\left\{\begin{array}{l@{\hskip10.0pt}l}1\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i=j,\\{} 0\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i\ne j.\end{array}\right.$
  • (2) $\forall i\in I$ $\forall j\in I$ $\operatorname{card}(X_{i}\cap X_{j})<c$ if $i\ne j$, where c denotes a power of continuum.
Definition 3.
The family $\{\mu _{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in I\}$ of probability measures is called weakly separable if there exists a family of S-measurable sets $\{X_{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in I\}$ such that the relations are fulfilled:
\[\forall i\in I\hspace{0.2778em}\forall j\in I\hspace{1em}\mu _{i}(X_{j})=\left\{\begin{array}{l@{\hskip10.0pt}l}1\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i=j,\\{} 0\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i\ne j.\end{array}\right.\]
Definition 4.
The family $\{\mu _{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in I\}$ of probability measures is called strongly separable if there exists a disjoint family of S-measurable sets $\{X_{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in I\}$ such that the relations are fulfilled: $\forall i\in I$ $\mu _{i}(X_{i})=1$.
Remark 1.
A strong separability implies separability, a separability implies a weak separability, and a weak separability implies orthogonality, but not vice versa.
Example 1.
Let $E=[0,1]\times [0,1]$, S be a Borel σ-algebra of subsets of E. Take the S-measurable sets $X_{i}=\{0\le x\le 1,\hspace{0.2778em}y=i,\hspace{0.2778em}i\in [0,1]\}$ and assume that $L_{i}$ are the linear Lebesgue probability measures on $X_{i}$. Then the family $\{L_{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in [0,1]\}$ is strongly separable.
Example 2.
Let $E=[0,1]\times [0,1]$, S be a Borel σ-algebra of subsets of E. Take the S-measurable sets
\[X_{i}=\big\{(x,y)\mid 0\le x\le 1,\hspace{0.2778em}y=i,\hspace{2.5pt}\text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i\in [0,1];\hspace{0.2778em}x=i-2,\hspace{0.2778em}0\le y\le 1,\hspace{2.5pt}\text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i\in [2,3]\big\}.\]
Let $L_{i}$ be the linear Lebesgue probability measures on $X_{i}$. Then the family $\{L_{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in [0,1]\cup [2,3]\}$ is separable but not strongly separable.
Example 3.
Let $E=[0,1]\times [0,1]\times [0,1]$, S be a Borel σ-algebra of subsets of E. Take the S-measurable sets:
\[\begin{array}{r@{\hskip0pt}l}\displaystyle X_{i}=\big\{(x,y,z)\mid \hspace{0.2778em}& \displaystyle 0\le x\le 1,\hspace{0.2778em}0\le y\le 1,\hspace{0.2778em}z=i,\hspace{2.5pt}\text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i\in [0,1];\\{} & \displaystyle x=i-2,\hspace{0.2778em}0\le y\le 1,\hspace{0.2778em}0\le z\le 1,\hspace{2.5pt}\text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i\in [2,3];\\{} & \displaystyle 0\le x\le 1,\hspace{0.2778em}y=i-4,\hspace{0.2778em}0\le z\le 1,\hspace{2.5pt}\text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i\in [4,5]\big\}.\end{array}\]
Let $L_{i}$ be the planar Lebesgue probability measures on $X_{i}$. Then the family $\{L_{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in [0,1]\cup [2,3]\cup [4,5]\}$ is weakly separable but not separable.
Example 4.
Let $E=[0,1]\times [0,1]$, S be a Borel σ-algebra of subsets of E. Take the S-measurable sets
\[X_{i}=\big\{(x,y)\mid 0\le x\le 1,\hspace{0.2778em}y=i,\hspace{0.2778em}i\in (0,1]\big\}.\]
Let $L_{i}$ be the linear Lebesgue probability measures on $X_{i}$ and $L_{0}$ be the planar Lebesgue probability measure on $E=[0,1]\times [0,1]$. Then the family $\{L_{i},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in [0,1]\}$ is orthogonal, but not weakly separable.
Definition 5.
We consider the notion of Hypothesis as any assumption that defines the form of the distribution selection.
Let H be set of hypotheses and $\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H})$ be σ-algebra of subsets of H which contains all finite subsets of H.
Definition 6.
The family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ is said to admit a consistent criteria of a hypothesis if there exists at least one measurable map $\delta :(E,S)\to (\mathrm{H},\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H}))$, such that $\mu _{H}(\{x\mid \delta (x)=H\})=1$, for all $H\in \mathrm{H}$.
Definition 7.
The following probability:
\[\alpha _{H}(\delta )=\mu _{H}\big(\big\{x\mid \delta (x)\ne H\big\}\big)\]
is called the probability of error of the H-th kind for a given criterion δ.
Definition 8.
The family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ is said to admit a consistent criterion of any parametric function if for any real bounded measurable function $g:(\mathrm{H},\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H}))\to \mathbb{R}$ there exists at least one measurable function $f:(E,S)\to \mathbb{R}$ such that $\mu _{H}(\{x\mid f(x)=g(H)\})=1$, for all $H\in \mathrm{H}$.
Definition 9.
The family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{2.5pt}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$is said to admit an unbiased criterion of any parametric function if for any real bounded measurable function $g:(\mathrm{H},\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H}))\to \mathbb{R}$ there exists at least one measurable function $\beta :(E,S)\to \mathbb{R}$, such that $\int _{E}\beta (x)\mu _{H}(dx)=g(H)$ for all $H\in \mathrm{H}$.
Remark 2.
If M is a family of probability measures admitting a consistent criterion for a hypothesis, then it is clear that M is a family of probability measures which admits a consistent criterion for any parametric function and a family of probability measures which admits an unbiased criterion of any parametric function.
Theorem 1.
The family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ admits a consistent criterion δ of a hypothesis if and only if the probability of error of all kinds is equal to zero for the criterion δ.
Proof.
Necessity. As the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ admits a consistent criterion of a hypothesis, so there exists such a measurable map $\delta :(E,S)\to (\mathrm{H},\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H}))$ that $\mu _{H}(\{x\mid \delta (x)=H\})=1$ for all $H\in \mathrm{H}$. It follows $\alpha _{H}(\delta )=\mu _{H}(\{x\mid \delta (x)\ne H\}=0$.
Sufficiency. As the probability of error of all kinds is equal to zero, so $\alpha _{H}(\delta )=\mu _{H}(\{x\mid \delta (x)\ne H\}=0$ for all $H\in \mathrm{H}$, we have
\[\big\{x\mid \delta (x)=H\big\}\cap \big\{x\mid \delta (x)={H^{\prime }}\big\}=\varnothing \]
for any $H\ne {H^{\prime }}$.
On the other hand $\{x\mid \delta (x)=H\}\cup \{x\mid \delta (x)\ne H\}=E$ and $\mu _{H}(\{x\mid \delta (x)=H\})=1$, for all $H\in \mathrm{H}$.
Therefore δ is a consistent criterion of a hypothesis. The Theorem 1 is proved.  □
Theorem 2.
Let $\mathrm{H}=\{H_{1},H_{2},\dots ,H_{n},\dots \}$ be the set of hypotheses. The family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$, $\mathbb{N}=\{1,2,\dots ,n,\dots \}$ admits the consistent criterion of hypotheses if and only if the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ is strongly separable.
Proof.
Necessity. Since the family $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ admits a consistent criterion of hypotheses, then there exists a measurable map δ of the space $(E,S)$ to $(\mathrm{H},\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H}))$ such that $\mu _{H_{i}}(x\mid \delta (x)=H_{i})=1$, $i\in \mathbb{N}$. Let $X_{i}=(x:\delta (x)=H_{i})$, then it is obvious, that $X_{i}\cap X_{i}\ne \varnothing $ for all $i\ne j$ and $\mu _{H_{i}}(X_{i})=1$, $\forall i\in \mathbb{N}$. Therefore, the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in N\}$ is strongly separable.
Sufficiency. As the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ is strongly separable, then there exist such pairwise disjoint S-measurable sets $X_{i}$, $i\in \mathbb{N}$ that $\mu _{H_{i}}(X_{i})=1$, $\forall i\in \mathbb{N}$.
Let’s define δ as such a mapping $(E,S)\to (\mathrm{H},\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H}))$ that $\delta (X_{i})=H_{i}$, $i\in \mathbb{N}$. We have $\{x:\delta (x)=H_{i}\}=X_{i}$ and $\mu _{H_{i}}\{x:\delta (x)=H_{i}\}=1$, $\forall i\in \mathbb{N}$. Therefore δ is a consistent criterion of hypotheses. The Theorem 2 is proved.  □
Theorem 3.
Let $\mathrm{H}=\{H_{1},H_{2},\dots ,H_{n},\dots \}$ and the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ be separable or weakly separable. Then the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ admits a consistent criterion of hypotheses.
Proof.
Since the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ is separable or weakly separable, then there exists a family $X_{1},X_{2},\dots ,X_{n},\dots $ of S-measures sets such that
\[\mu _{H_{i}}(X_{j})=\left\{\begin{array}{l@{\hskip10.0pt}l}1,\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i=j,\\{} 0,\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i\ne j.\end{array}\right.\]
Let us consider the sets:
\[\begin{array}{r@{\hskip0pt}l}& \displaystyle \overline{X}_{1}=X_{1}-X_{1}\cap \bigg(\bigcup \limits_{k\ne 1}X_{k}\bigg)\\{} & \displaystyle \overline{X}_{2}=X_{2}-X_{2}\cap \bigg(\bigcup \limits_{k\ne 2}X_{k}\bigg)\\{} & \displaystyle \hspace{1em}\dots \\{} & \displaystyle \overline{X}_{n}=X_{n}-X_{n}\cap \bigg(\bigcup \limits_{k\ne n}X_{k}\bigg)\\{} & \displaystyle \hspace{1em}\dots \end{array}\]
It is obvious that $\{\overline{X}_{1},\overline{X}_{2},\dots ,\overline{X}_{n},\dots \}$ is a disjoint family of S-measurable sets and $\mu _{H_{i}}(\overline{X}_{i})=1$, $\forall i\in \mathbb{N}$. Therefore, the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ is strongly separable and $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ admits a consistent criterion of hypotheses by the Theorem 1. The Theorem 3 is proved.  □
Theorem 4.
Let $\mathrm{H}=\{H_{1},H_{2},\dots ,H_{n},\dots \}$ and the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ $\mathbb{N}=\{1,2,\dots ,n,\dots \}$ be orthogonal (singular). Then the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ admits a consistent criterion of hypotheses.
Proof.
The singularity of probability measures implies an existence of the family $\{X_{ik}\}$ of S-measurable sets such that for any $i\ne k$ we have $\mu _{H_{k}}(X_{ik})=0$ and $\mu _{H_{i}}(E-X_{ik})=0$.
Let us consider the sets $X_{i}=\bigcup _{k\ne i}(E-X_{ik})$, then
\[\mu _{H_{i}}(X_{i})=\mu _{H_{i}}\bigg(\bigcup \limits_{k\ne i}(E-X_{ik})\bigg)\le \sum \limits_{k\ne i}\mu _{H_{i}}(E-X_{ik})=0.\]
Therefore, $\mu _{H_{i}}(X_{i})=0$; $\mu _{H_{i}}(E-X_{i})=1$. On the other hand, for $k\ne i$ we have $\mu _{H_{k}}(E-X_{i})=0$. This means that the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ is weakly separable. By the Theorem 3 this family of probability measures admits a consistent criterion of hypotheses. The Theorem 4 is proved.  □
It follows from the Theorems 3, 4, that for the countable family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ the notions of weakly separable, separable, orthogonal and strong separable are equivalent.

2 Consistent criteria in Banach space

Let ${M}^{\sigma }$ be a real linear space of all alternating finite measures on S.
Definition 10.
A linear subset $M_{B}\subset {M}^{\sigma }$ is called a Banach space of measures if:
  • (1) a norm can be defined on $M_{B}$ so that $M_{B}$ will be a Banach space with respect to this norm, and for any orthogonal measures $\mu ,\nu \in M_{B}$ and any real number $\lambda \ne 0$ the inequality $\| \mu +\lambda \nu \| \ge \| \mu \| $ is fulfilled;
  • (2) if $\mu \in M_{B}$, $|\hspace{0.1667em}f(x)|\le 1$, than $\nu _{f}(A)=\int _{A}f(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu (dx)\in M_{B}$, and $\| \nu _{f}\| \le \| \nu \| $, where $f(x)$ is a real measurable function, $A\in S$;
  • (3) if $\nu _{n}\in M_{B}$, $\nu _{n}>0$, $\nu _{n}(E)<\infty $, $n=1,2,\dots $ and $\nu _{n}\downarrow 0$, then for any linear functional ${l}^{\ast }\in {M_{B}^{\ast }}$
    \[\underset{n\to \infty }{\lim }{l}^{\ast }(\nu _{n})=0.\]
The construction of the Banach space of measures is studied in paper [8]. The following theorem have also been proved in this paper:
Theorem 5.
Let $M_{B}$ be a Banach space of measures, then in $M_{B}$ there exists a family of pairwise orthogonal probability measures $\{\mu _{i},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in I\}$ such that
\[M_{B}=\underset{i\in I}{\bigoplus }M_{B}(\mu _{i}),\]
where $M_{B}(\mu _{i})$ is the Banach space of elements ν of the form:
\[\nu (B)=\int _{B}f(x)\mu _{i}\hspace{0.1667em}(dx),\hspace{1em}B\in S,\hspace{2em}\int _{E}\big|\hspace{0.1667em}f(x)\big|\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{i}(dx)<\infty ,\]
with the norm
\[\| \nu \| _{M_{B}(\mu _{i})}=\int _{E}\big|\hspace{0.1667em}f(x)\big|\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{i}(dx).\]
Let $\{H_{i}\}$ be a countable family of hypotheses. Denote by $F=F(M_{B})$ the set of real functions f for which $\int _{E}f(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{i}}(dx)$ is defined for all $\mu _{H_{i}}\in M_{B}$, where $M_{B}=\bigoplus _{i\in \mathbb{N}}M_{B}(\mu _{H_{i}})$.
Theorem 6.
Let $M_{B}=\bigoplus _{i\in \mathbb{N}}M_{B}(\mu _{H_{i}})$ be a Banach space of measures. The family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ admits a consistent criteria of hypotheses if and only if the correspondence $f\to l_{f}$ defined by the equality
\[\int _{E}f(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H}(dx)=l_{f}(\mu _{H}),\hspace{1em}\forall \mu _{H}\in M_{B},\]
is one-to-one.
Here $l_{f}$ is the linear functional on $M_{B}$, $f\in F(M_{B})$.
Proof.
Sufficiency. For $f\in F(M_{B})$ we define the linear continuous functional $l_{f}$ by the equality $\int _{E}f(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H}dx)=l_{f}(\mu _{H})$. Denote as $I_{f}$ a countable subset in $\mathbb{N}$, for which $\int _{E}f(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{i}}(dx)=0$ for $i\notin I_{f}$. Let us consider the functional $l_{f_{H_{i}}}$ on $M_{B}(\mu _{H_{i}})$ to which it corresponds. Then for $\mu _{H_{1}},\mu _{H_{2}}\in M_{B}(\mu _{H_{i}})$ we have:
\[\int _{E}f_{H_{1}}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H}(dx)=l_{f_{H_{1}}}(\mu _{H_{2}})=\int _{E}f_{1}(x)f_{2}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{i}}(dx)=\int f_{H_{1}}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{i}}(dx).\]
Therefore $f_{H_{1}}=f_{1}$ a.e. with respect to the measure $\mu _{H_{i}}$. Let $f_{H_{i}}>0$ a.e. with respect to the measure $\mu _{H_{i}}$ and
\[\int _{E}f_{H_{i}}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{i}}(dx)<\infty ,\hspace{2em}\mu _{H_{i}}(C)=\int _{C}f_{H_{i}}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{i}}(dx),\]
then
\[\int _{E}f_{H_{i}}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{j}}(dx)=l_{f_{H_{i}}}(\mu _{H_{j}})=0,\hspace{1em}\forall j\in \mathbb{N}.\]
Denote $C_{H_{i}}=\{x\mid f_{H_{i}}(x)>0\}$, then $\int _{E}f_{H_{i}}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{j}}(dx)=l_{f_{H_{i}}}(\mu _{H_{j}})=0$, $\forall j\in \mathbb{N}$. Hence it follows, that $\mu _{H_{j}}(C_{H_{i}})=0$, $\forall j\in \mathbb{N}$. On the other hand $\mu _{H_{i}}(E-C_{H_{i}})=0$. Therefore the family $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ is weekly separable and
\[\mu _{H_{i}}(C_{H_{j}})=\left\{\begin{array}{l@{\hskip10.0pt}l}1,\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i=j,\\{} 0,\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i\ne j.\end{array}\right.\]
Let us consider the sets $\overline{C}_{H_{i}}=C_{H_{i}}\diagdown C_{H_{i}}\cap \bigcup _{k\ne i}C_{H_{k}}$. It is obvious that $\{\overline{C}_{H_{i}},i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ is a disjunctive family of S-measurable sets and $\mu _{H_{i}}(C_{H_{i}})=1$, $\forall i\in \mathbb{N}$. Let us define a mapping $\delta :(E,S)\to (\mathrm{H},\mathrm{B}(H))$ like that $\delta (\overline{C}_{H_{i}})=H_{i}$, $\forall i\in \mathbb{N}$. We have $\mu _{H_{i}}(\{x\mid \delta (x)=H_{i}\})=1$, $\forall i\in \mathbb{N}$. Therefore δ is a consistent criterion of hypotheses.
Necessity. Since the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ admits a consistent criterion of hypotheses and this family is strongly separable, so there exist S-measurable sets $X_{i}$, $i\in \mathbb{N}$, such that
\[\mu _{H_{i}}(X_{j})=\left\{\begin{array}{l@{\hskip10.0pt}l}1,\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i=j,\\{} 0,\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}i\ne j.\end{array}\right.\]
We put the linear continuous functional $l_{X_{i}}$ into the correspondence to a function $I_{X_{i}}\in F(M_{\beta })$ by the formula:
\[\int _{E}I_{X_{i}}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{i}}(dx)=l_{I_{X_{i}}}(\mu _{H_{i}})=\| \mu _{H_{i}}\| _{M_{\beta }(\mu _{H_{i}})}.\]
We put the linear continuous functional $l_{f_{H_{1}}}$ into the correspondence to the function
\[f_{H_{1}}(x)=f_{1}(x)I_{X_{i}}(x)\in F(M_{\beta }).\]
Then for any $\mu _{H_{2}}\in M_{B}(\mu _{i})$
\[\begin{array}{r@{\hskip0pt}l}\displaystyle \int _{E}f_{H_{1}}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{2}}(dx)& \displaystyle =\int _{E}f_{1}(x)I_{X_{i}}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{2}}(dx)=\int _{E}f(x)f_{1}(x)I_{X_{i}}(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{i}}(dx)\\{} & \displaystyle =l_{f_{H_{1}}}(\mu _{H_{2}})=\| \mu _{H_{2}}\| _{M_{B}(\mu _{H_{i}})}.\end{array}\]
Let $\varSigma =\{l_{f}\}$ be the collection of extensions of the functional $l_{f_{_{H_{1}}}}:M_{\beta }(\mu _{_{H_{1}}})\to R$ satisfying the condition $l_{f}\le p(x)$ on those subspaces where they are defined.
Let us introduce a partial ordering on Σ having assumed $l_{f_{1}}<l_{f_{2}}$ if $l_{f_{2}}$ is defined on a larger set than $l_{f_{1}}$ and $l_{f_{1}}(\mu )=l_{f_{2}}(\mu )$ where both of them are defined.
Let $\{l_{f_{i}}\}_{i\in I}$ be a linear ordered subset in Σ. Let $M_{B}(\mu _{_{H_{i}}})$ be the subspace on which $l_{_{f_{H_{i}}}}$ is defined. Define $l_{f}$ on $\bigoplus _{i\in I}M_{B}(\mu _{_{H_{i}}})$, having assumed $l_{f}(\mu )=l_{_{f_{H_{i}}}}(\mu )$ if $\mu \in M_{B}(\mu _{_{H_{i}}})$.
It is obvious, that $l_{f_{H_{i}}}<l_{f}$. Since any linearly ordered subset in Σ has an upper bound, by virtue of Zorn lemma Σ contains a maximal element λ defined on some set ${X^{\prime }}$ satisfying the condition $\lambda (x)\le p(x)$ for $x\in {X^{\prime }}$. But ${X^{\prime }}$ must coincide with the entire space $M_{B}$ because otherwise we could extend λ to a wider space by adding, as above, one more dimension.
This contradicts with the maximality of λ and hence ${X^{\prime }}=M_{B}$. Therefore the extension of the functional is defined everywhere.
If we put the linear continuous functional $l_{f}$ into the correspondence to the function
\[f(x)=\sum \limits_{i\in \mathbb{N}}g_{H_{i}}(x)I_{X_{i}}(x)\in F(M_{B}),\]
then we obtain
\[\int _{E}f(x)\mu _{H}(dx)=\| \mu _{H}\| =\sum \limits_{i\in \mathbb{N}}\| \mu _{H_{i}}\| _{M_{B}(\mu _{H_{i}})},\]
where $\mu _{H}=\sum _{i\in N}\int _{E}g_{H_{i}}\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H_{i}}(dx)$. The Theorem 6 is proved.  □
Remark 3.
It follows from the proven theorem that the indicated above correspondence puts some functions $f\in F(M_{B})$ into the correspondence to each linear continuous functional $l_{f}$. If in $F(M_{\beta })$ we identify functions coinciding with respect to the measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$, then the correspondence will be bijective.
In what follows $\mathrm{B}(E,S)$ will always denote a vector space formed by all real bounded measurable functions on $(E,S)$ having the natural order. It is an $(AN)$-space with identity according to which a function is identically equal to one on E (see [5]). Let ${\mathrm{B}^{\prime }}(E,S)$ denote the topological conjugate space of $\mathrm{B}(E,S)$, which is an order-complete Banach lattice. The elements of ${\mathrm{B}^{\prime }}(E,S)$ are called finitely-additive measures on $(E,S)$ and the canonical bilinear form which puts $\mathrm{B}(E,S)$ and ${\mathrm{B}^{\prime }}(E,S)$ in duality is denoted by
\[\langle f,\mu \rangle =\mu (f)=\int _{E}f(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu (dx),\hspace{1em}f\in \mathrm{B}(E,S),\hspace{2.5pt}\mu \in {\mathrm{B}^{\prime }}(E,S)\]
and called the integral of f with respect to μ. In what follows $\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H},B(\mathrm{H}))$ is the space of measurable bounded functions and ${\mathrm{B}^{\prime }}(\mathrm{H},B(\mathrm{H}))$ is the conjugate space of all finitely-additive measures on $(\mathrm{H},B(\mathrm{H}))$.
Equal units of $\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H},B(\mathrm{H}))$ space are denoted by $e_{\mathrm{H}}$ and elements $\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H},B(\mathrm{H}))$ and ${\mathrm{B}^{\prime }}(\mathrm{H},B(\mathrm{H}))$ are denoted by g and ν respectively. Intersection of $\{\nu \in {\mathrm{B}^{\prime }}(\mathrm{H},\mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H}))\mid \langle e_{\mathrm{H}},\nu \rangle =1\}$ and positive cone is denoted by $S_{\mathrm{H}}$. It is clear that $S_{\mathrm{H}}$ is a compact subset of the simple share, so a set of extreme points of this cone is not empty.
It is also well known that in the (ZFC), (CH), (MA) theory there exists a continual weekly separable family of probability measures which is not strongly separable. Here and in the sequel we denote by (MA) the Martin’s axiom (see [3]).
Theorem 7.
Let $M_{B}=\bigoplus _{H\in \mathrm{H}}M_{B}(\mu _{H})$ be the Banach space of measures, E be the complete separable metric space, S be the Borel σ-algebra in E and $\operatorname{card}\mathrm{H}\le c$. Then in the theory (ZFC) and (MA) the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ admits a consistent criteria of hypotheses if and only if the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ admits an unbiased criterion of any parametric function and the correspondence $f\to l_{f}$ by the equality
\[\int _{E}f(x)\mu _{H}(dx)=l_{f}(\mu _{H}),\hspace{1em}\forall \mu _{H}\in M_{B}\]
is one-to-one. Here $l_{f}$ is a linear continuous functional on $M_{B}$, $f\in F(M_{B})$.
Proof.
Necessity. As the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ admits a consistent criterion of hypotheses, so the family $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ admits an unbiased criterion of any parametric function and it is strongly separable. So, the family $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ is weekly separable. The necessity is proved in the same manner as the necessity of the Theorem 6.
Sufficiency. According to the Theorem 6 a Borel orthogonal family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$, $\operatorname{card}\mathrm{H}\le c$ is weakly separable. We represent $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ as an inductive sequence $\mu _{H}<\omega _{\alpha }$, where $\omega _{\alpha }$ denotes the first ordinal number of the power of the set H. Since the family $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ is weakly separable, there exists a family of measurable parts $\{X_{H}\}_{H<\omega _{\alpha }}$ of the space E, such that the following relations are fulfilled:
\[\mu _{H}(X_{{H^{\prime }}})=\left\{\begin{array}{l@{\hskip10.0pt}l}1,\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}H={H^{\prime }},\\{} 0,\hspace{1em}& \text{if}\hspace{2.5pt}H\ne {H^{\prime }}\end{array}\right.\]
for all $H\in [0,\omega _{\alpha })$ and ${H^{\prime }}\in [0,\omega _{\alpha })$.
We define $\omega _{\alpha }$-sequence of parts $B_{H}$ of the space E so that the following relations are fulfilled:
  • (1) $B_{H}$ is a Borel subset in E for all $H<\omega _{\alpha }$.
  • (2) $B_{H}\subset X_{H}$ for all $H<\omega _{\alpha }$.
  • (3) $B_{H}\cap B_{{H^{\prime }}}=\varnothing $ for all $H<\omega _{\alpha }$, ${H^{\prime }}<\omega _{\alpha }$, $H\ne {H^{\prime }}$.
  • (4) $\mu _{H}(B_{H})=1$ for all $H<\omega _{\alpha }$.
Assume that $B_{0}=X_{0}$. Let further the partial sequence $\{B_{{H^{\prime }}}\}_{{H^{\prime }}<H}$ be already defined for $H<\omega _{\alpha }$.
It is clear, that ${\mu }^{\ast }(\bigcup _{{H^{\prime }}<H}B_{{H^{\prime }}})=0$. Thus there exists a Borel subset $Y_{H}$ of the space E, such that the following relations are valid: $\bigcup _{{H^{\prime }}<H}B_{{H^{\prime }}}\subset Y_{H}$ and $\mu (Y_{H})=0$. Assume $B_{H}=X_{H}\setminus Y_{H}$, thereby the $\omega _{\alpha }$ sequence of $\{B_{H}\}_{H<\omega _{\alpha }}$ disjunctive measurable subsets of the space E is constructed. Therefore $\mu _{H}(B_{H})=1$ for all $H<\omega _{\alpha }$. As a family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ admits an unbiased criterion for any parametric function, so there exists a subspace $G\subset \mathrm{B}(E,S)$, containing $e_{E}$ unit and $\mathrm{B}(E,S)$ can be imagine as a topological sum of G and $H_{0}={\mu }^{-1}(0)$, where the functional
\[\mu (f)=\int _{E}f(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu (dx),\hspace{1em}f\in \mathrm{B}(E,S),\hspace{2.5pt}\mu \in {\mathrm{B}^{\prime }}(E,S)\]
and a family $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ is strongly separable, subspace G is a grid towards canonical order on G (see [5]). We assume that $S_{0}$ is a minimal σ-algebra of subalgebra S, all function on G are measurable towards $S_{0}$. Then $G\subset B(E,S_{0})\subset B(E,S)$.
Since a subspace G contains $e_{E}$ and represents a grid, then $G\supset B(E,S)$ and that’s why $G=B(E,S)$.
As family $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ represents a dense subspace of $exS_{H}$ ($exS_{H}$ are extreme points of $S_{H}$), so $I_{\mu }$ is an ideal in the set $S_{0}$ which contains zero measured sets for all $\mu \in \{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ and consists only of an empty set.
Hence there exist such sets $\{A_{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ that $\mu _{H}(A_{H})=1$ and $A_{H}\cap A_{{H^{\prime }}}=\varnothing $ for a $H\ne H_{0}$ and $E=\bigcup _{H\in \mathrm{H}}A_{H}$ is a set $S_{0}$. It follows from the condition of this theorem that for every $T\in \mathrm{B}(\mathrm{H})$ in G there exists $f_{T}$ function, which is a consistent criterion of $g_{T}$ parametric function. If $A=\{x\mid f_{t}(x)\ne 0\}$, then $\bigcup _{H\in T}A_{H}\subset A$, $A\cap A_{H}=\varnothing $ for all $H\notin T$ and hence $\bigcup _{H\in T}A_{H}=A$ implying that $\bigcup _{H\in T}A_{H}\subset S_{0}$.
Then, the mapping $\delta (x)=H$ if $x\in A_{H}$ for all $H\in \mathrm{H}$ is a consistent criterion of hypotheses. The theorem is proved.  □

References

[1] 
Borovkov, A.A.: Mathematical Statistics. Nauka, Moscow (1984). English translation, Gordon and Breach, Amsterdam (1998)
[2] 
Ibramkhalilov, Sh. Skorokhod A. V, I.: Consistent Estimates of Parameters of Random Processes. Naukova Dumka, Kiev (1980)
[3] 
Jech, T.: Set Theory. Springer, Berlin (2003). MR1940513
[4] 
Kharazishvili, A.B.: Topological Aspects of Measure Theory. Naukova Dumka, Kiev (1984). MR0784614
[5] 
Maleev, M., Serechenko, A., Tarashchanskii, M.: Family of probability measures admitting consistent estimators. In: Skorokhod, A.V. (ed.) Probability Distributions in Infinite Dimensional Spaces, pp. 125–134. Institute of Mathematics of Acad. Sci. Ukrainian SSR, Kiev (1978)
[6] 
Zerakidze, Z.: On weakly divisible and divisible families of probability measures. Bull. Acad. Sci. Georgian SSR 113(2), 273–275 (1984). MR0780715
[7] 
Zerakidze, Z.: On consistent estimators for families of probability measures. In: 5-th Japan–USSR Symposium on Probability Theory, Kyoto, pp. 62–63 (1986)
[8] 
Zerakidze, Z.S.: Banach space of measures. In: Grigelionis, B., et al. (eds.) Probability Theory and Mathematical Statistics: Proceedings of the Fifth Vilnius Conference, Vilnius, vol. 2, VSP/Mokslas, pp. 609–616 (1991). MR1153917
Reading mode PDF XML

Table of contents
  • 1 Basic notions and consistent criterion on hypothesis for countable family of probability measures
  • 2 Consistent criteria in Banach space
  • References

Copyright
© 2014 The Author(s). Published by VTeX
by logo by logo
Open access article under the CC BY license.

Keywords
Consistent criteria singular orthogonal weakly separable strongly separable probability measures

MSC2010
62H05 62H12

Metrics
since March 2018
502

Article info
views

290

Full article
views

312

PDF
downloads

169

XML
downloads

Export citation

Copy and paste formatted citation
Placeholder

Download citation in file


Share


RSS

  • Theorems
    7
Theorem 1.
Theorem 2.
Theorem 3.
Theorem 4.
Theorem 5.
Theorem 6.
Theorem 7.
Theorem 1.
The family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ admits a consistent criterion δ of a hypothesis if and only if the probability of error of all kinds is equal to zero for the criterion δ.
Theorem 2.
Let $\mathrm{H}=\{H_{1},H_{2},\dots ,H_{n},\dots \}$ be the set of hypotheses. The family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{2.5pt}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$, $\mathbb{N}=\{1,2,\dots ,n,\dots \}$ admits the consistent criterion of hypotheses if and only if the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ is strongly separable.
Theorem 3.
Let $\mathrm{H}=\{H_{1},H_{2},\dots ,H_{n},\dots \}$ and the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ be separable or weakly separable. Then the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ admits a consistent criterion of hypotheses.
Theorem 4.
Let $\mathrm{H}=\{H_{1},H_{2},\dots ,H_{n},\dots \}$ and the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ $\mathbb{N}=\{1,2,\dots ,n,\dots \}$ be orthogonal (singular). Then the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ admits a consistent criterion of hypotheses.
Theorem 5.
Let $M_{B}$ be a Banach space of measures, then in $M_{B}$ there exists a family of pairwise orthogonal probability measures $\{\mu _{i},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in I\}$ such that
\[M_{B}=\underset{i\in I}{\bigoplus }M_{B}(\mu _{i}),\]
where $M_{B}(\mu _{i})$ is the Banach space of elements ν of the form:
\[\nu (B)=\int _{B}f(x)\mu _{i}\hspace{0.1667em}(dx),\hspace{1em}B\in S,\hspace{2em}\int _{E}\big|\hspace{0.1667em}f(x)\big|\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{i}(dx)<\infty ,\]
with the norm
\[\| \nu \| _{M_{B}(\mu _{i})}=\int _{E}\big|\hspace{0.1667em}f(x)\big|\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{i}(dx).\]
Theorem 6.
Let $M_{B}=\bigoplus _{i\in \mathbb{N}}M_{B}(\mu _{H_{i}})$ be a Banach space of measures. The family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H_{i}},\hspace{0.2778em}i\in \mathbb{N}\}$ admits a consistent criteria of hypotheses if and only if the correspondence $f\to l_{f}$ defined by the equality
\[\int _{E}f(x)\hspace{0.1667em}\mu _{H}(dx)=l_{f}(\mu _{H}),\hspace{1em}\forall \mu _{H}\in M_{B},\]
is one-to-one.
Here $l_{f}$ is the linear functional on $M_{B}$, $f\in F(M_{B})$.
Theorem 7.
Let $M_{B}=\bigoplus _{H\in \mathrm{H}}M_{B}(\mu _{H})$ be the Banach space of measures, E be the complete separable metric space, S be the Borel σ-algebra in E and $\operatorname{card}\mathrm{H}\le c$. Then in the theory (ZFC) and (MA) the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ admits a consistent criteria of hypotheses if and only if the family of probability measures $\{\mu _{H},\hspace{0.2778em}H\in \mathrm{H}\}$ admits an unbiased criterion of any parametric function and the correspondence $f\to l_{f}$ by the equality
\[\int _{E}f(x)\mu _{H}(dx)=l_{f}(\mu _{H}),\hspace{1em}\forall \mu _{H}\in M_{B}\]
is one-to-one. Here $l_{f}$ is a linear continuous functional on $M_{B}$, $f\in F(M_{B})$.

MSTA

MSTA

  • Online ISSN: 2351-6054
  • Print ISSN: 2351-6046
  • Copyright © 2018 VTeX

About

  • About journal
  • Indexed in
  • Editors-in-Chief

For contributors

  • Submit
  • OA Policy
  • Become a Peer-reviewer

Contact us

  • ejournals-vmsta@vtex.lt
  • Mokslininkų 2A
  • LT-08412 Vilnius
  • Lithuania
Powered by PubliMill  •  Privacy policy