Modern Stochastics: Theory and Applications logo


  • Help
Login Register

  1. Home
  2. Issues
  3. Volume 10, Issue 1 (2023)
  4. Minimax identity with robust utility fun ...

Minimax identity with robust utility functional for a nonconcave utility
Volume 10, Issue 1 (2023), pp. 19–35
Olena Bahchedjioglou ORCID icon link to view author Olena Bahchedjioglou details   Georgiy Shevchenko  

Authors

 
Placeholder
https://doi.org/10.15559/22-VMSTA215
Pub. online: 28 October 2022      Type: Research Article      Open accessOpen Access

Received
11 July 2022
Revised
25 September 2022
Accepted
12 October 2022
Published
28 October 2022

Abstract

The minimax identity for a nondecreasing upper-semicontinuous utility function satisfying mild growth assumption is studied. In contrast to the classical setting, concavity of the utility function is not asumed. By considering the concave envelope of the utility function, equalities and inequalities between the robust utility functionals of an initial utility function and its concavification are obtained. Furthermore, similar equalities and inequalities are proved in the case of implementing an upper bound on the final endowment of the initial model.

1 Introduction

Consider a complete market model framework with the unique equivalent local martingale measure ${Q^{e}}$. In the spirit of Reichlin [19], we consider a utility function U on ${\mathbb{R}_{+}}$ which is nondecreasing upper-semicontinuous and satisfying a mild growth condition. Schied and Wu [21] impose the below assumptions on the set of probability measures $\mathcal{Q}$ on $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F})$; note that $\mathcal{Q}$ is not the set of all measures on the measurable space $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F})$, but just a subset satisfying these assumptions.
Assumption 1.
  • (i) $\mathcal{Q}$ is convex;
  • (ii) $\mathbb{P}[A]=0$ if and only if $Q[A]=0$ for all $Q\in \mathcal{Q}$;
  • (iii) The set $\mathcal{Z}:=\{dQ/d\mathbb{P}|Q\in \mathcal{Q}\}$ is closed in ${L^{0}}(\mathbb{P})$.
Also, to Assumption 1 we add
  • (iv) The set ${\mathcal{Z}_{e}}:=\{dQ/dP|Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}\}$ is closed in ${L^{0}}(\mathbb{P})$,
where ${\mathcal{Q}_{e}}$ denotes the set of measures in $\mathcal{Q}$ that are equivalent to $\mathbb{P}$.
In this paper we study the minimax identity for the robust nonconcave utility functional in a complete market model, i.e.
\[ u(x):=\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[U(X)]=\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[U(X)],\]
while considering two possibilities for the set $\mathcal{X}(x)$ of admissible final endowments:
  • • the standard budget constraint:
    \[ \mathcal{X}(x)=\{X\in {L_{+}^{1}}({Q^{e}})|{\mathrm{E}_{{Q^{e}}}}[X]\le x\},\hspace{1em}x>0,\]
  • • an additional upper bound:
    (1)
    \[ {\mathcal{X}^{W}}(x)=\{X\in {L^{1}}({Q^{e}})\mid 0\le X\le W,{\mathrm{E}_{{Q^{e}}}}[X]\le x\},\]
    with some random variable $W:\Omega \to [0,+\infty )$.
One of the key tasks of financial mathematics is proving the existence as well as the construction of optimal investment strategies, in other words, finding the utility-maximizing investment strategies. Mostly, this problem was studied under the assumption that the probability distribution of the value process is known.
However, in reality, along with the exact probabilities unknown, there are abundant aspects that can be considered in mentioned maximization problems such as the completeness of the market, the set of prior probability measures, the assumptions on investor’s utility function, the modeling of payoff and so on. That is why instead of a single measure it is sound to consider the set of probability measures with natural assumptions on it. Thus, the standard utility maximization problem becomes the robust utility maximization problem
\[ \underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{\mathrm{E}_{Q}}[U(X)],\]
where one maximizes the expected utility under the infimum over the whole set of probability measures, for details see Gilboa and Schmeidler [9, 10, 22], Yaari [25], Föllmer and Schied [8, Section 2.5].
In the case of a standard utility maximization problem it is possible to construct the optimal investment strategy given a strictly concave utility function, see Föllmer and Schied [8, Section 2.5], and for the general utility functions, see Bahchedjioglou and Shevchenko [4]. Both references considered standard budget constraints as well as an additional upper bound on the final endowments. For a detailed survey of this problem in a general model setup in both complete and incomplete market models but with risk-averse agent, see Biagini [6].
In this paper, we consider the robust maximization problem with the general nonconcave utility function, with and without budget constraints likewise. In the previous literature different approaches were used for robust portfolio optimization such as reducing the robust case to the standard one through proving the existence of the “worst-case scenario measure” or “the least favorable measure”, e.g., [17, 20], a stochastic control approach, see [11], an approach using BSDEs, see [7] and references therein.
Besides, for solving the optimal investment problems one can make use of the following interim finding such as minimax identity and duality theory. Using the minimax identity for concave functions, see [1, section 6], Schied and Wu [21] showed the existence of an optimal probability measure $\widehat{Q}$ in the sense that
\[ \underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{\mathrm{E}_{Q}}[U({X_{T}})]=\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }{\mathrm{E}_{\widehat{Q}}}[U({X_{T}})],\]
which, together with the results of the Kramkov and Schachermayer [13, 14], was the base for proving the existence of the optimal investment strategy. They used a general incomplete market model with rather natural assumptions on the set of probability measures. Backhoff Veraguas and Fontbona [3] extended these results by implementing the assumption on the densities of the uncertainty set instead of the usual compactness assumption. Moreover, they have done this without relying on the existence of the worst-case measure or on any assumption implying this.
Neufeld and Šikić [15, 16] studied a robust stochastic optimization problem in the quasi-sure setting in discrete time. Their paper [15] deals with the study of general concave utility functions, showing the existence of the maximizer in different market models under the linearity-type condition, which is caused by the no-arbitrage condition. In [16], they consider the nonconcave utility maximization problem and outline the conditions of maximizer’s existence.
For more results concerning the robust utility maximization problem we refer to Bartl, Kupper and Neufeld [5] and references therein.
The majority of articles on utility maximization assume that the investor’s utility function is strictly concave, strictly increasing, continuously differentiable, and satisfies the Inada conditions. While the assumption of monotonicity is natural, since an agent prefers more wealth to less, other assumptions can be omitted or relaxed. There is a wide class of models in which the maximization of the nonconcave and not necessarily continuously differentiable utility function has been studied by reducing the problem to the concave case. One of the most important works was done by Reichlin [18, 19]. He considered the general framework of nonconcave utility functions for both complete and incomplete market models. By applying the concavification technique he established valuable relations between the maximization problems for a nonconcave utility function U and its concavification ${U_{c}}$ thereby reducing the task to the concave problem. Moreover, Reichlin proved the existence of the maximizer under certain assumptions and established its properties.
While considering two cases of admissible final endowments – the standard budget constraint and additional upper bound (which has not been considered before in such model setup) – we extend Reichlin’s results by proving new connections in the form of equalities and inequalities of the robust utility maximization functionals of initial nonconcave utility functions and its concavification. Furthermore, we proceed in proving the minimax identity for general nonconcave utility functions. The crucial step for obtaining the mentioned results with implementing an additional upper bound is the use of the regular conditional distribution which sheds new light on the possible approaches for solving the optimization problem.
The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2 we study the minimax identity for a nonconcave utility function in the complete market model. We do not prove nor refute the minimax identity, however, we show useful equalities and inequalities to relate the robust utility functional of initial utility function and its concavification. Section 3 is devoted to the study of the minimax identity under the implementation of budget constraints. The results of Section 3 are similar to the corresponding results of Section 2, however, some of proves differ significantly.
Throughout the paper the measurability of real-valued functions is understood in the Borel sense.

2 Minimax identity for nonconcave utility functions in complete market model

This problem is already solved in [12], but, since we want to expand this problem by considering budget constraints, we present the main part of the mentioned paper omitting the proofs.

2.1 Formulation of the problem

To formulate the goal of this paper first let us remind some notations. For any initial capital $x>0$, let $\mathcal{X}(x)$ be the set of all possible random endowments corresponding to x, i.e. all random variables X such that $X\ge 0$, ${\mathrm{E}_{{Q^{e}}}}[X]\le x$.
Moreover, we consider a utility function U which is nondecreasing, upper-semicontinuous, defined on a domain $(0,\infty )$ and satisfying the mild growth condition:
\[ \underset{x\to \infty }{\lim }\frac{U(x)}{x}=0.\]
It follows from [2, Proposition 3.1] that $U(x)$ has a nondecreasing and continuous concave envelope ${U_{c}}(x)$, or the smallest concave function such that ${U_{c}}(x)\ge U(x)$ for all $x\in \mathbb{R}$; we will call it a concavification of U.
This section aims to prove some equalities and inequalities related to the minimax identity for the robust nonconcave utility functionals:
\[ \underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[U(X)]=\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[U(X)].\]
We will assume that the probability space $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F},\mathbb{P})$ is atomless. Introduce the notation:
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle {u^{c}}(x):=\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}}(X)];\\ {} \displaystyle {u_{Q}}(x):=\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[U(X)];\\ {} \displaystyle {u_{Q}^{c}}(x):=\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}}(X)].\end{array}\]
Also, we need the finiteness of value functions, which we can write as follows.
Assumption 2.
\[ \text{For all}\hspace{2.5pt}x>0\text{, there exists a measure}\hspace{2.5pt}{Q_{0}}\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}\hspace{2.5pt}\text{such that}\hspace{2.5pt}{u_{{Q_{0}}}}(x)<\infty .\]
Assumption 3.
\[ {u_{{Q_{0}}}^{c}}(x)<\infty \hspace{2.5pt}\text{for some, and hence for all}\hspace{2.5pt}x>0\hspace{2.5pt}\text{and some}\hspace{2.5pt}{Q_{0}}\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}.\]
Note that finiteness of ${u_{Q}^{c}}(x)$ implies finiteness of ${u_{Q}}(x)$, since ${u_{Q}}(x)\le {u_{Q}^{c}}(x)$.
Theorem 1.
Suppose that Assumptions 1, 2, 3 hold and that the probability space $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F},\mathbb{P})$ is atomless.
Then the following holds: vmsta215_g001.jpg
The proof of this theorem will be divided into several parts.

2.2 Minimax identity for the concavified objective function ${U_{c}}(x)$

Now we are going to show that the minimax identity holds for ${U_{c}}(x)$.
There is a lot of literature with proofs of the minimax identity for robust utility functionals, the most general case was considered in [21]. However, there the authors assume that the utility function is strictly increasing, strictly concave, and satisfies the Inada conditions both at point 0 and at ∞.
The function ${U_{c}}(\cdot )$ which we are considering is no longer strictly concave and does not satisfy the Inada conditions at 0, hence we cannot use all the previous results without changes.
The next lemma is almost the same as [21, Lemma 3.4].
Lemma 1.
Suppose that Assumption 1 and Assumption 3 hold.
Then we have
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle {u^{c}}(x)=\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}}(X)]=\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}}(X)]\\ {} \displaystyle =\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}}(X)]=\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}}(X)].\end{array}\]
Remark.
This lemma holds if we will consider utility function $U:(0,\infty )\to \mathbb{R}$ instead of $U:[0,\infty )\to \mathbb{R}$. Thus, we present the proof for a more general case.
Proof.
The proof can be found in [12, Lemma 1].  □

2.3 Minimax identity for the objective function $U(x)$

In this section, we want to prove lemmas which will help us to complete the proof of Theorem 1.
Remark.
Note that the main argument in the proof of minimax identity for the robust utility maximization problem is the lop sided minimax theorem by Aubin and Ekeland, see [1, Chapter 6, p. 295], which holds if the functional $X\to \mathbb{E}[ZU(X)]$ is concave. Since we consider the nonconcave utility function U, we cannot prove the minimax identity in this case similarly. A more general case of the minimax identity was proved by Maurice Sion, see [24]. However, to use Sion’s minimax theorem we still need functional $X\to \mathbb{E}[ZU(X)]$ to be quasi-concave, which is not true, in the general case, even for the indicator functions multiplied by the constants.
Lemma 2.
If Assumption 1 and Assumption 2 hold, then for all $X\in \mathcal{X}(x)$
(2)
\[ \underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[U(X)]=\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[U(X)].\]
Proof.
The proof can be found in [12, Lemma 2].  □
Remark 1.
The above lemma also holds for ${U_{c}}$ in place of U.
The proof of equality $(5\mathrm{\star })$ is based on [19, Theorem 5.1].
Lemma 3.
Suppose that $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F},\mathbb{P})$ is atomless.
Then it holds that
\[ \underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[U(X)]=\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }\underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}}(X)].\]
Proof.
The proof can be found in [12, Lemma 3].  □
Proof of Theorem 1.
  • • $(1\mathrm{\star })$–$(3\mathrm{\star })$ follows from Lemma 1;
  • • $(4\mathrm{\star })$ follows from the fact that ${U_{c}}\ge U$;
  • • $(5\mathrm{\star })$ follows from Lemma 3;
  • • To obtain $(6\mathrm{\star })$ we need to take the $\underset{g\in C(x)}{\sup }$ of the both sides in equality (2);
  • • Inequality $(7\mathrm{\star })$ follows from the fact that for all $Q\in \mathcal{Q}$ and all $X\in \mathcal{X}(x)$ it holds
    \[ \underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[U(X)]\le \underset{X\in \mathcal{X}(x)}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[U(X)].\]
  • • Since ${\mathcal{Q}_{e}}\subseteq \mathcal{Q}$, inequality $(8\mathrm{\star })$ is clear.
 □

3 Minimax identity for constrained case of random endowments

3.1 Formulation of the problem

This section is in general similar to Section 2, however, similarly to [8, Chapter 3] we consider a modified constrained counterpart.
Specifically, we assume that there is an upper bound on the endowment, given by a random variable $W:\Omega \to (0,+\infty )$. The set of admissible payoffs is then given by
\[ {\mathcal{X}^{W}}:=\{X\in {L^{0}}(\mathbb{P})\mid 0\le X\le W\hspace{2.5pt}\mathbb{P}\text{-a.s.}\}.\]
As it was pointed out in [8, Chapter 3], such formulation arises in various applications. For instance, we can consider an agent who aims at reaching a certain random final wealth W; this may be the future price of certain asset or the claim that agent will have to pay. In this situation, additional utility for any amount above W is zero, while the agent still applies her utility function for endowments below W. Since we assume completeness, there is no reason to consider endowments X, which exceed W with positive probability, as they can safely be replaced by $X\wedge W$.
We keep all of the assumptions from Section 2 on the set of all probability measures $\mathcal{Q}$ and the utility function U intact. For technical reasons we will also assume that $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F})$ is a standard Borel space, which in particular implies the existence of a regular conditional distribution given W. We will require that this conditional distribution is atomless, in other words, that the constraint W leaves a sufficient amount of randomness.
Assumption 4.
  • 1. $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F})$ is a standard Borel space.
  • 2. There exists a regular conditional distribution given W, which is atomless, i.e. there exists a function $P:\mathcal{F}\times (0,\infty )\to [0,\infty )$ such that for all $v>0$, $P(\cdot ,v)$ is an atomless probability measure, and for all $A\in \mathcal{F}$, $P(A,\cdot )$ is a measurable function satisfying $P(A,W)=\mathbb{P}(A\mid W)$ a.s.
Remark 2.
A simple sufficient condition for $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F})$ to be Borel is that $\mathcal{F}$ is generated by a collection of real-valued random variables, which is sufficient for the majority of applications. Since we assume market completeness, this assumptions is automatically fulfilled as long as one does not consider completion of $\mathcal{F}$.
The second assumption is verified if, for example, on $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F},\mathbb{P})$ there is a random variable which is independent of W and has continuous distribution, so it does not seem to be too restrictive. We also stress that it does not contradict the market completeness; the simplest example is a market with two independent continuously distributed assets ${S^{1}},{S^{2}}$ and $W=f({S^{1}})$.
As in [4], for each $k>0$ denote
(3)
\[ {U^{k}}(x)=U(x\wedge k),\hspace{1em}x\ge 0.\]
Note that the function ${U^{k}}$ and its concavification ${U_{c}^{k}}$ satisfy all of the assumptions on the utility function U and its concavification ${U_{c}}$. Moreover, ${U_{c}^{k}}(x)={U^{k}}(x)$, for all $x\ge k$.
Our goal is to prove some equalities and inequalities related to the minimax identity for the robust nonconcave utility functionals
\[ \underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W(\omega )}}(X)]=\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W(\omega )}}(X)]\]
with the budget set ${\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$ defined by
\[ {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}:=\{X\in {L^{1}}({Q^{e}})\mid 0\le X\le W,{E_{{Q^{e}}}}[X]\le x\},\]
where $x>0$ is the initial wealth and ${Q^{e}}$ is the unique equivalent local martingale measure.
Introduce the following notation:
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle {u_{c}^{W}}(x):=\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)];\\ {} \displaystyle {u_{Q}^{W}}(x):=\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W(\omega )}}(X)];\\ {} \displaystyle {u_{c,Q}^{W}}(x):=\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)].\end{array}\]
Remark.
Since ${U^{k}}(x)\le U(x)$, $x\ge 0$, Assumptions 2 and 3 provide the finiteness of the value function above.
It is natural to consider only the case where
(4)
\[ {\mathrm{E}_{{Q^{e}}}}[W]>x,\]
as otherwise, thanks to the monotonicity of U, the optimization problem has a trivial solution ${X^{\ast }}=W$.
The formulation of the next theorems and lemmas are the same as in Section 2. However, because of the boundness assumption on the endowments the proof of the corresponding statements will be different.
Theorem 2.
Under Assumptions 1, 2, 3, 4, we have the following:
vmsta215_g002.jpg
The proof of this theorem will be divided into several parts.

3.2 Minimax identity for the concavified objective function ${U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(x)$

Now we are going to show that minimax identity holds for ${U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(x)$. First we prove some useful properties.
Lemma 4.
  • a) The set ${\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$ is convex.
  • b) It holds that ${u_{c}^{W}}(x)=\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]$ is concave.
Proof.
  • a) Consider ${X_{1}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{1}}}^{W}}$ and ${X_{2}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{2}}}^{W}}$ for some ${x_{1}},{x_{2}}>0$ and $\alpha \in (0,1)$. One has that $0\le \alpha {X_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){X_{2}}\le W$ and ${\mathrm{E}_{{Q^{e}}}}[\alpha {X_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){X_{2}}]\le \alpha {x_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){x_{2}}$. Hence, $\alpha {X_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){X_{2}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{\alpha {x_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){x_{2}}}^{W}}$.
  • b) Take ${X_{1}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{1}}}^{W}}$ and ${X_{2}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{2}}}^{W}}$ for some ${x_{1}},{x_{2}}>0$ and $\alpha \in (0,1)$.
    Then, noting that $\{\alpha {X_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){X_{2}}|{X_{1}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{1}}}^{W}},{X_{2}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{2}}}^{W}}\}\subset {\mathcal{X}_{\alpha {x_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){x_{2}}}^{W}}$, one has
    \[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle {u_{c}^{W}}(\alpha {x_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){x_{2}})=\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{\alpha {x_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){x_{2}}}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]\\ {} \displaystyle \ge \underset{\alpha {X_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){X_{2}}|{X_{1}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{1}}}^{W}},{X_{2}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{2}}}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(\alpha {X_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){X_{2}})]\\ {} \displaystyle \ge \underset{\alpha {X_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){X_{2}}|{X_{1}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{1}}}^{W}},{X_{2}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{2}}}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[\alpha {U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}({X_{1}})+(1-\alpha ){U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}({X_{2}})]\\ {} \displaystyle \ge \underset{\alpha {X_{1}}+(1-\alpha ){X_{2}}|{X_{1}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{1}}}^{W}},{X_{2}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{2}}}^{W}}}{\sup }[\alpha \underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}({X_{1}})]\\ {} \displaystyle +(1-\alpha )\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}({X_{2}})]]\\ {} \displaystyle =\alpha \underset{{X_{1}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{1}}}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}({X_{1}})]+(1-\alpha )\underset{{X_{2}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{{x_{2}}}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}({X_{2}})]\\ {} \displaystyle =\alpha {u_{c}^{W}}({x_{1}})+(1-\alpha ){u_{c}^{W}}({x_{2}}).\end{array}\]
 □
Lemma 5.
Suppose that Assumption 1 and Assumption 3 hold.
Then we have
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle {u_{c}^{W}}(x)=\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]=\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]\\ {} \displaystyle =\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]=\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)].\end{array}\]
Proof.
Take $\varepsilon >0$. Consider $Y:=(X+\varepsilon )\wedge W$, for $X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$. Then $Y\in {\mathcal{X}_{x+\varepsilon }^{W}}$, since $0\le Y\le W$ and ${\mathrm{E}_{{Q^{e}}}}[Y]={\mathrm{E}_{{Q^{e}}}}[(X+\varepsilon )\wedge W]\le {\mathrm{E}_{{Q^{e}}}}[X+\varepsilon ]\le x+\varepsilon $.
Define ${Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}:=\{Y\in {L^{1}}({Q^{e}})\mid Y=(X+\varepsilon )\wedge W,X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}\}$. Then ${Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}\subset {\mathcal{X}_{x+\varepsilon }^{W}}$. Thus, it holds that
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle {u_{c}^{W}}(x+\varepsilon )=\underset{\bar{X}\in {\mathcal{X}_{x+\varepsilon }^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(\bar{X})]\\ {} \displaystyle \ge \underset{Y\in {Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(Y)]=\underset{Y\in {Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }\mathbb{E}\left[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(Y)\cdot \frac{dQ}{dP}\right]\\ {} \displaystyle =\underset{Y\in {Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Z\in \mathcal{Z}}{\inf }\mathbb{E}[Z{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(Y)].\end{array}\]
In the proof of [12, Lemma 1] it is already shown that for each $X\in \mathcal{X}(x)$ the map $Z\mapsto \mathbb{E}[Z{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(Y)]$ is a weakly lower-semicontinuous affine functional defined on the weakly compact convex set $\mathcal{Z}$.
Moreover, in the proof of [12, Lemma 1] it is already shown that for each $Z\in \mathcal{Z}$, $X\to \mathbb{E}[Z{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X+\varepsilon )]$ is a concave functional. Hence, one has that for each $Z\in \mathcal{Z}$, $X\to \mathbb{E}[Z{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(Y)]$ is a concave functional defined on the convex set ${\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$.
Noting that weak convergence follows from almost sure convergence, the conditions of the lop sided minimax theorem [1, Chapter 6, p. 295] are satisfied, and so
\[ \underset{Y\in {Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Z\in \mathcal{Z}}{\min }\mathbb{E}[Z{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(Y)]=\underset{Z\in \mathcal{Z}}{\min }\underset{Y\in {Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}}{\sup }\mathbb{E}[Z{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(Y)].\]
Hence, we arrive at
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle {u_{c}^{W}}(x+\varepsilon )\ge \underset{Y\in {Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Z\in \mathcal{Z}}{\inf }\mathbb{E}[Z{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(Y)]=\underset{Z\in \mathcal{Z}}{\min }\underset{Y\in {Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}}{\sup }\mathbb{E}[Z{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(Y)]\\ {} \displaystyle \ge \underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }\underset{Y\in {Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(Y)]\\ {} \displaystyle \stackrel{Y\ge X}{\ge }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }\underset{Y\in {Y_{X,\varepsilon }^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]\ge \underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]={u_{c}^{W}}(x).\end{array}\]
The last inequality follows from the fact that for all $Q\in \mathcal{Q}$ and $X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$
\[ \underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]\ge \underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)].\]
Sending $\varepsilon \downarrow 0$ and using the continuity of ${u_{c}^{W}}$, as a concave function on the set $(0,+\infty )$, we obtain the first part of the lemma.
From Assumption 3 and [21, Lemma 3.3] it follows that ${u_{c}^{W}}(x)=\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }{u_{c,Q}^{W}}(x)$ (the proof is similar to the proof of [12, Lemma 2]).
Hence,
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle {u_{c}^{W}}(x)=\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }{u_{c,Q}^{W}}(x)=\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]\\ {} \displaystyle \ge \underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]\ge \underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }\underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]={u_{c}^{W}}(x).\end{array}\]
This concludes the proof.  □

3.3 Minimax identity for the objective function $U(x)$

In this section, we will establish auxiliary results which will allow us to complete the proof of Theorem 2.
Lemma 6.
If Assumption 1 and Assumption 2 hold, then for all $X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$
(5)
\[ \underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W}}(X)]=\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W}}(X)].\]
Proof.
The proof is the same as in the nonconstrained case. See [12, Lemma 2].  □
Lemma 7.
Let $\{{P_{v}},v\in (0,\infty )\}$ be a family of atomless probability measures on a standard Borel space $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F})$, such that for any $A\in \mathcal{F}$, ${P_{\cdot }}(A)$ is measurable. Then, for all $Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}$, for all $X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$, there exists ${X^{\mathrm{\star }}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$ such that
(6)
\[ {E_{Q}}[{U^{W}}({X^{\mathrm{\star }}})]={E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W}}({X^{\mathrm{\star }}})]={E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W}}(X)]\ge {E_{Q}}[{U^{W}}(X)].\]
Proof.
The main idea of the proof is to utilize the ideas of [19, Proposition 5.3] in our conditional setting.
Fix $Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}$ and define $\psi =d{Q^{e}}/d\mathbb{P}$, $\varphi =d{Q^{e}}/dQ$. First of all, note that for any $Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}$, there exists a corresponding regular conditional probability given W. Indeed, since ψ is positive, $M(v):={\textstyle\int _{\Omega }}\psi \hspace{0.1667em}P(d\omega ,v)$ is positive as well, so
\[ {P_{Q}}(A,v)=\frac{{\textstyle\int _{A}}\psi \hspace{0.1667em}P(d\omega ,v)}{M(v)},\hspace{1em}A\in \mathcal{F},\]
is a probability measure. It is easy to see that it is measurable in v and ${P_{Q}}(A,W)=Q(A\mid W)$ Q-a.s.
By Lemma 13 applied to $Y(x,\omega )=X(\omega )$, $\phi (v,\omega )=\varphi (\omega )$ and ${P_{v}}(A)={P_{Q}}(A,v)$, there exists a jointly measurable function ${Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )$ such that for all $v>0$, ${E_{{P_{Q}}(\cdot ,v)}}[{Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )\varphi (\omega )]\le {E_{{P_{Q}}(\cdot ,v)}}[X(\omega )\varphi (\omega )]$ and
\[ {E_{{P_{Q}}(\cdot ,v)}}[{U^{v}}\big({Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )\big)]={E_{{P_{Q}}(\cdot ,v)}}[{U_{c}^{v}}\big({Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )\big)]={E_{{P_{Q}}(\cdot ,v)}}[{U_{c}^{v}}\big(X(\omega )\big)].\]
Set ${X^{\mathrm{\star }}}(\omega )={Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(W(\omega ),\omega )$. Then
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle {E_{{Q^{e}}}}\left[{X^{\mathrm{\star }}}\right]={E_{Q}}\left[{Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}\big(W(\omega ),\omega \big)\varphi \right]={E_{Q}}\left[{E_{Q}}\left[{Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}\big(W(\omega ),\omega \big)\varphi \mid W\right]\right]\\ {} \displaystyle ={E_{Q}}\left[{E_{{P_{Q}}(\cdot ,v)}}[{Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )\varphi (\omega )]{\big|_{v=W}}\right]\le {E_{Q}}\left[{E_{{P_{Q}}(\cdot ,v)}}[X(\omega )\varphi (\omega )]{\big|_{v=W}}\right]\\ {} \displaystyle ={E_{Q}}\left[{E_{Q}}\left[X(\omega )\varphi \mid W\right]\right]={E_{Q}}\left[X(\omega )\varphi \right]={E_{{Q^{e}}}}[X]\le x,\end{array}\]
so ${X^{\mathrm{\star }}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$. Further,
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle {E_{Q}}\left[{U_{c}^{W}}({X^{\mathrm{\star }}})\right]={E_{Q}}\left[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}\big({Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(W(\omega ),\omega )\big)\right]\\ {} \displaystyle ={E_{Q}}\left[{E_{Q}}\left[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}\big({Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(W(\omega ),\omega )\big)\mid W\right]\right]\\ {} \displaystyle ={E_{Q}}\left[{E_{{P_{Q}}(\cdot ,v)}}[{U_{c}^{v}}\big({Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )\big)]{\big|_{v=W}}\right]={E_{Q}}\left[{E_{{P_{Q}}(\cdot ,v)}}[{U_{c}^{v}}\big(X(\omega )\big)]{\big|_{v=W}}\right]\\ {} \displaystyle ={E_{Q}}\left[{E_{Q}}\left[{U_{c}^{v}}\big(X(\omega )\big)\mid W\right]\right]={E_{Q}}\left[{U_{c}^{v}}\big(X(\omega )\big)\right].\end{array}\]
The equality ${E_{Q}}[{U^{W}}({X^{\mathrm{\star }}})]={E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W}}({X^{\mathrm{\star }}})]$ is proved similarly, and the inequality ${E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W}}(X)]\ge {E_{Q}}[{U^{W}}(X)]$ is obvious, since ${U_{c}^{W}}\ge {U^{W}}$. The proof is now complete.  □
Lemma 8.
If Assumption 4 holds, then for all $Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}$ it holds that
\[ \underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W(\omega )}}(X)]=\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)],\hspace{1em}\textit{for all}\hspace{2.5pt}x>0.\]
Proof.
Apply the $\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }$ to the all parts of (6). Then one has
(7)
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle \underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W(\omega )}}({X^{\mathrm{\star }}})]=\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}({X^{\mathrm{\star }}})]\\ {} \displaystyle =\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)]\ge \underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W(\omega )}}(X)].\end{array}\]
Since $Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}$ is arbitrary, $X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$ is arbitrary and ${X^{\mathrm{\star }}}\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$, it follows that the inequality in (7) is an equality and, hence, the statement of the lemma is proven.  □
Lemma 9.
Under Assumption 4,
\[ \underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W(\omega )}}(X)]=\underset{Q\in {\mathcal{Q}_{e}}}{\inf }\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}(X)].\]
Proof.
Follows immediately from Lemma 8.  □
Proof of Theorem 2.
  • • $(1\mathrm{\star })$–$(3\mathrm{\star })$ follows from Lemma 5;
  • • $(4\mathrm{\star })$ follows from the fact that ${U_{c}^{W(\omega )}}\ge {U^{W(\omega )}}$;
  • • $(5\mathrm{\star })$ follows from Lemma 9;
  • • To obtain $(6\mathrm{\star })$ we need to take the $\underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }$ of the both sides of equality (5);
  • • Inequality $(7\mathrm{\star })$ follows from the fact that for all $Q\in \mathcal{Q}$ and all $X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}$ it holds that
    \[ \underset{Q\in \mathcal{Q}}{\inf }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W(\omega )}}(X)]\le \underset{X\in {\mathcal{X}_{x}^{W}}}{\sup }{E_{Q}}[{U^{W(\omega )}}(X)].\]
  • • Since ${\mathcal{Q}_{e}}\subseteq \mathcal{Q}$, inequality $(8\mathrm{\star })$ is clear.
 □

A Auxiliary statements

In what follows $U:{\mathbb{R}_{+}}\to {\mathbb{R}_{+}}$ is a nondecreasing upper-semicontinuous function satisfying a mild growth condition, ${U^{v}}(y)=U(y\wedge v)$, $v>0$, and ${U_{c}^{v}}$ is the concavification of ${U^{v}}$. For $v>y>0$, let
\[ a(v,y)=\left\{\begin{array}{l@{\hskip10.0pt}l}\inf \{z\le y:{U_{c}^{v}}(x)>{U^{v}}(x)\hspace{2.5pt}\text{on}\hspace{2.5pt}[z,y]\},\hspace{1em}& {U^{v}}(y)<{U_{c}^{v}}(y),\\ {} y,\hspace{1em}& {U^{v}}(y)={U_{c}^{v}}(y),\end{array}\right.\]
and
\[ b(v,y)=\left\{\begin{array}{l@{\hskip10.0pt}l}\sup \{z\le y:{U_{c}^{v}}(x)>{U^{v}}(x)\hspace{2.5pt}\text{on}\hspace{2.5pt}[y,z]\},\hspace{1em}& {U^{v}}(y)<{U_{c}^{v}}(y),\\ {} y,\hspace{1em}& {U^{v}}(y)={U_{c}^{v}}(y),\end{array}\right.\]
be the left and right endpoints of the interval around y, in which ${U^{v}}<{U_{c}^{v}}$ (or just y in the case where ${U^{v}}(y)={U_{c}^{v}}(y)$). Observe that ${U^{v}}(a(v,y))={U_{c}^{v}}(a(v,y))$. Indeed, if ${U^{v}}(a(v,y))<{U_{c}^{v}}(a(v,y))$, then ${U^{v}}<{U_{c}^{v}}$ in some open interval around $a(v,y)$, contradicting the definition of infimum. Similarly, ${U^{v}}(b(v,y))={U_{c}^{v}}(b(v,y))$.
Lemma 10.
The functions a and b defined above are measurable.
Proof.
We will show only measurability of a, that of b can be shown similarly.
Note that a is obviosly nondecreasing in y. It is also right-continuous in y. Indeed, let ${y_{n}}\ge {y_{0}}$, ${y_{n}}\to {y_{0}}$, $n\to \infty $. If ${U^{v}}({y_{0}})<{U_{c}^{v}}({y_{0}})$, then, thanks to continuity of ${U_{c}^{v}}$ and upper-semicontinuity of ${U^{v}}$, this inequality holds in an open interval around ${y_{0}}$, which means that $a(v,{y_{n}})=a(v,{y_{0}})$ for all n large enough. Otherwise, if ${U^{v}}({y_{0}})={U_{c}^{v}}({y_{0}})$, then $a(v,{y_{n}})\in ({y_{0}},{y_{n}}]$ for all $n\ge 1$, whence $a(v,{y_{n}})\to {y_{0}}=a(v,{y_{0}})$, $n\to \infty $.
Further, since for ${v_{1}}<{v_{2}}$, ${U_{c}^{{v_{2}}}}$ dominates ${U^{{v_{1}}}}$ on $[0,{v_{1}}]$, we have that ${U_{c}^{{v_{2}}}}\ge {U_{c}^{{v_{1}}}}$. Consequently, a is nonincreasing in v. Now the proof follows from the following lemma.
Lemma 11.
Let a function $f:{(0,\infty )^{2}}\to \mathbb{R}$ be such that for each $x>0$, $f(x,\cdot )$ is nondecreasing and right-continuous, and for each $y>0$, $f(\cdot ,y)$ is nondecreasing. Then f is measurable.
Proof.
For arbitrary $t\in \mathbb{R}$ consider the set ${A_{t}}={f^{-1}}((-\infty ,t))$. Thanks to monotonicity, $(x,y)\in {A_{t}}\Rightarrow ({x^{\prime }},{y^{\prime }})\in {A_{t}}$ for all ${x^{\prime }}\le x,{y^{\prime }}\le y$. Moreover, thanks to right-continuity in y, the x-sections ${A_{t,x}}=\{y>0:(x,y)\in {A_{t}}\}$ are open intervals.
Define ${A_{t,x+}}={\textstyle\bigcup _{z>x}}{A_{t,z}}$. We claim that the set ${A_{t}^{o}}:=\{(x,y)\in {(0,\infty )^{2}}:y\in {A_{t,x+}}\}$ is open (it is actually the interior of ${A_{t}}$). Indeed, if $(x,y)\in {A_{0}^{t}}$, then $y\in {A_{t,z}}$ for some $z>x$. Since ${A_{t,z}}$ is open, for some $\varepsilon >0$, $(y-\varepsilon ,y+\varepsilon )\subset {A_{t,z}}$. Then, thanks to monotonicity, $(0,z)\times (y-\varepsilon ,y+\varepsilon )\subset {A_{t}^{0}}$.
By the definition of ${A_{t}^{o}}$,
\[ {A_{t}}\setminus {A_{t}^{o}}=\bigcup \limits_{x>0}\{x\}\times ({A_{t,x}}\setminus {A_{t,x+}}).\]
For any $x>0$, ${A_{t,x}}\setminus {A_{t,x+}}$ is a difference of two open intervals, so it’s either a half-open interval or empty. Since the half-open intervals for different x are disjoint, there are at most countable number of then. Therefore, ${A_{t}}\setminus {A_{t}^{o}}$ is Borel as a countable union of Borel sets, which finishes the proof.  □
 
Lemma 12.
Let $\{{P_{v}},v\in (0,\infty )\}$ be a family of atomless probability measures on a standard Borel space $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F})$, such that for any $A\in \mathcal{F}$, ${P_{\cdot }}(A)$ is measurable. Let also $\xi :(0,\infty )\times \Omega \to \mathbb{R}$ be measurable. Then, there exist measurable functions $\zeta :(0,\infty )\times \Omega \to \mathbb{R}$ and $q:(0,\infty )\times \mathbb{R}\to \mathbb{R}$ such that for all $v\in (0,\infty )$, $\zeta (v,\cdot )$ has a uniform distribution on $(0,1)$ with respect to ${P_{v}}$, $q(v,\cdot )$ is nondecreasing, and $q(v,\zeta (v,\omega ))=\xi (v,\omega )$  ${P_{v}}$-a.s.
Proof.
Since $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F})$ carries an atomless measure, it is uncountable. Then it is well known that it is isomorphic to $(\mathbb{R},\mathcal{B}(\mathbb{R}))$, i.e. there exists a measurable bijection $\tau :\Omega \to \mathbb{R}$ such that ${\tau ^{-1}}$ is measurable as well. Therefore we can assume without loss of generality that $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F})=\big((0,1),\mathcal{B}((0,1))\big)$.
Assume first that the distribution of $\xi (v,\omega )$ is continuous for all $v\in (0,\infty )$. The cumulative distribution function ${F_{\xi }}(v,x)={P_{v}}(\{\xi (v,\omega )\le x\})$ is jointly measurable (see, e.g., [23, Lemma 4.1]), so the quantile function ${q_{\xi }}(v,r)=\inf \{x\in \mathbb{R}:{F_{\xi }}(v,x)\ge r\}$ is jointly measurable as well. So in this case we can set $\zeta (v,\omega )={F_{\xi }}(v,\xi (v,\omega ))$ and $q(v,r)={q_{\xi }}(v,r)$; by the quantile transformation theorem, ζ and q are as required.
For general ξ, define
\[ \kappa (v,x)={P_{v}}(\{\omega :\xi (v,\omega ) < x\})+{P_{v}}(\{\omega \le x:\xi (v,\omega )=\xi (v,x)\}),\hspace{1em}x\in (0,1),\]
which is jointly measurable thanks to [23, Lemma 4.1]. It is easy to see that for any $v\in (0,\infty )$, κ has continuous distribution under ${P_{v}}$, and
\[ {q_{\xi }}(v,\kappa (v,\omega ))=\xi (v,\omega ),\]
where, as above, ${q_{\xi }}$ is the quantile function of ξ. Then we can set $\zeta (v,\omega )={F_{\kappa }}(v,\kappa (v,\omega ))$ and $q(v,r)={q_{\xi }}(v,{q_{\kappa }}(v,r))$, arriving at the desired statement.  □
Lemma 13.
Let $\{{P_{v}},v\in (0,\infty )\}$ be a family of atomless probability measures on a standard Borel space $(\Omega ,\mathcal{F})$, such that for any $A\in \mathcal{F}$, ${P_{\cdot }}(A)$ is measurable. Also let $Y,\phi :(0,\infty )\times \Omega \to [0,\infty )$ be jointly measurable functions such that $Y(v,\omega )\le v$ for all $v>0$, $\omega \in \Omega $. Then, there exists a jointly measurable function ${Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )$ such that for all $v>0$, ${E_{{P_{v}}}}[{Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )\phi (v,\omega )]\le {E_{{P_{v}}}}[Y(v,\omega )\phi (v,\omega )]$ and
\[ {E_{{P_{v}}}}[{U^{v}}\big({Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )\big)]={E_{{P_{v}}}}[{U_{c}^{v}}\big({Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )\big)]={E_{{P_{v}}}}[{U_{c}^{v}}\big(Y(v,\omega )\big)].\]
Proof.
We will adapt the construction used in the proof of [19, Proposition 5.3] so that it has the desired measurability property.
Define
\[ S=\{(v,\omega )\in (0,\infty )\times \Omega :{U^{v}}(Y(v,\omega ))<{U_{c}^{v}}(Y(v,\omega ))\},\]
and for $(v,\omega )\in S$, let
\[\begin{array}{l}\displaystyle \alpha (v,\omega ):=\inf \{z:{U^{v}}(x)<{U_{c}^{v}}(x)\hspace{2.5pt}\text{on}\hspace{2.5pt}(z,X(\omega )]\},\\ {} \displaystyle \beta (v,\omega ):=\sup \{z:{U^{v}}(x)<{U_{c}^{v}}(x)\hspace{2.5pt}\text{on}\hspace{2.5pt}[X(\omega ),z)\}\end{array}\]
be the left and the right ends of the interval on which ${U^{v}}<{U_{c}^{v}}$. These functions are measurable thanks to Lemma 10.
For $(v,\omega )\in S$, define
\[ \lambda (v,\omega )=\frac{\beta (v,\omega )-X(\omega )}{\beta (v,\omega )-\alpha (v,\omega )}\]
so that $X(v,\omega )=\lambda (v,\omega )\alpha (v,\omega )+(1-\lambda (v,\omega ))\beta (v,\omega )$. Due to Lemma 12, there exist measurable functions $\zeta ,q:(0,\infty )\times \Omega \to \mathbb{R}$ such that for all $v>0$, $\phi (v,\omega )=q(v,\zeta (v,\omega ))$ ${P_{v}}$-a.s. and $\zeta (v,\omega )$ is uniformly distributed on $(0,1)$ under ${P_{v}}$. For $s\in [0,1]$, $v>0$ and $\omega ,{\omega ^{\prime }}\in \Omega $, define
\[ h(s,v,\omega ,{\omega ^{\prime }})={\mathbb{I}_{(v,X(\omega ))\in S,(v,X({\omega ^{\prime }}))\in S,a(v,X(\omega ))=a(v,X({\omega ^{\prime }}))}}\big({\mathbb{I}_{\zeta (v,{\omega ^{\prime }}) < s}}-\lambda (v,{\omega ^{\prime }})\big)\]
and
\[ f(s,v,\omega )={\int _{\Omega }}h(v,\omega ,{\omega ^{\prime }},s){P_{v}}(d{\omega ^{\prime }}).\]
Since $\lambda (v,\omega )\in (0,1)$ and ζ has continuous distribution under ${P_{v}}$, we have that for all $(v,\omega )\in S$, f is continuous in s and $f(0,v,\omega ) < 0 < f(1,v,\omega )$. Denoting $\sigma (v,\omega )=\inf \{s\in (0,1):f(s,v,\omega )\ge 0\}$, we have $f(\sigma (v,\omega ),v,\omega )=0$. Also for any $s\in (0,1)$, $\{(v,\omega ):\sigma (v,\omega )\le s\}=\{(v,\omega ):f(s,v,\omega )\ge 0\}$, so $\sigma (v,\omega )$ is measurable.
Now set
\[ {Y^{\mathrm{\star }}}(v,\omega )=\left\{\begin{array}{l@{\hskip10.0pt}l}Y(v,\omega ),\hspace{1em}& (v,\omega )\notin S;\\ {} \alpha (v,\omega ),\hspace{1em}& (v,\omega )\in S\cap \{\zeta (v,\omega )<\sigma (v,\omega )\};\\ {} \beta (v,\omega ),\hspace{1em}& (v,\omega )\in S\cap \{\zeta (v,\omega )\ge \sigma (v,\omega )\}.\end{array}\right.\]
Since for any fixed $v>0$ the construction coincides with that given in [19, Proposition 5.3], the rest of the proof follows.  □

Acknowledgement

O. Bahchedjioglou thanks Prof. Dr. Mitja Stadje and Dr. Thai Nguyen for their help and support during her work on the topic.
Authors thank the anonymous reviewer for careful reading of the manuscript and helpful suggestions.

References

[1] 
Aubin, J.-P., Ekeland, I.: Applied Nonlinear Analysis. Pure and Applied Mathematics (New York), p. 518. John Wiley & Sons, Inc., New York (1984). A Wiley-Interscience Publication. MR0749753
[2] 
Aumann, R.J., Perles, M.: A variational problem arising in economics. J. Math. Anal. Appl. 11, 488–503 (1965). MR0182447. https://doi.org/10.1016/0022-247X(65)90100-9
[3] 
Backhoff Veraguas, J.D., Fontbona, J.: Robust utility maximization without model compactness. SIAM J. Financ. Math. 7(1), 70–103 (2016) MR3466196. https://doi.org/10.1137/140985718
[4] 
Bahchedjioglou, S.G. O.: Optimal investments for the standard maximization problem with non-concave utility function in complete market model. Math. Methods Oper. Res. 95(5), 163–181 (2022). MR4397208. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00186-022-00774-0
[5] 
Bartl, D., Kupper, M., Neufeld, A.: Duality theory for robust utility maximisation. Finance Stoch. 25(3), 469–503 (2021) MR4283309. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00780-021-00455-6
[6] 
Biagini, S.: Expected Utility Maximization: Duality Methods. John Wiley & Sons, Ltd (2010). https://doi.org/10.1002/9780470061602.eqf04009.
[7] 
Bordigoni, G., Matoussi, A., Schweizer, M.: A stochastic control approach to a robust utility maximization problem. In: Stochastic Analysis and Applications, pp. 125–151. Springer (2007) MR2397786. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-540-70847-6_6
[8] 
Föllmer, H., Schied, A.: Stochastic Finance. De Gruyter (2016). MR3859905. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110463453
[9] 
Gilboa, I.: Expected utility with purely subjective non-additive probabilities. J. Math. Econ. 16(1), 65–88 (1987). MR0885821. https://doi.org/10.1016/0304-4068(87)90022-X
[10] 
Gilboa, I., Schmeidler, D.: Maxmin expected utility with non-unique prior. In: Uncertainty in Economic Theory, pp. 141–151. Routledge (2004) MR1000102. https://doi.org/10.1016/0304-4068(89)90018-9
[11] 
Hernández-Hernández, D., Schied, A.: A control approach to robust utility maximization with logarithmic utility and time-consistent penalties. Stoch. Process. Appl. 117(8), 980–1000 (2007) MR2340875. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.spa.2006.11.005
[12] 
Kharytonova, O.O.: Duality theory under model uncertainty for non-concave utility functions. Bull. Taras Shevchenko Nat. Univ. Kyiv. Ser. Phys. Math. 4, 50–56 (2019). https://doi.org/10.17721/1812-5409.2019/4.6
[13] 
Kramkov, D., Schachermayer, W.: The asymptotic elasticity of utility functions and optimal investment in incomplete markets. Ann. Appl. Probab. 9(3), 904–950 (1999). MR1722287. https://doi.org/10.1214/aoap/1029962818
[14] 
Kramkov, D., Schachermayer, W.: Necessary and sufficient conditions in the problem of optimal investment in incomplete markets. Ann. Appl. Probab. 13(4), 1504–1516 (2003). MR2023886. https://doi.org/10.1214/aoap/1069786508
[15] 
Neufeld, A., Šikić, M.: Robust utility maximization in discrete-time markets with friction. SIAM J. Control Optim. 56(3), 1912–1937 (2018) MR3807937. https://doi.org/10.1137/16M1101829
[16] 
Neufeld, A., Šikić, M.: Nonconcave robust optimization with discrete strategies under knightian uncertainty. Math. Methods Oper. Res. 90(2), 229–253 (2019) MR4031791. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00186-019-00669-7
[17] 
Quenez, M.-C.: Optimal portfolio in a multiple-priors model. In: Seminar on Stochastic Analysis, Random Fields and Applications IV, pp. 291–321 (2004). Springer MR2096294
[18] 
Reichlin, C.: Non-concave utility maximization: optimal investment, stability and applications. PhD thesis, ETH Zürich (2012). https://doi.org/10.3929/ethz-a-007615699
[19] 
Reichlin, C.: Utility maximization with a given pricing measure when the utility is not necessarily concave. Math. Financ. Econ. 7(4), 531–556 (2013) MR3092304. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11579-013-0093-x
[20] 
Schied, A.: Optimal investments for robust utility functionals in complete market models. Math. Oper. Res. 30(3), 750–764 (2005). MR2161208. https://doi.org/10.1287/moor.1040.0138
[21] 
Schied, A., Wu, C.-T.: Duality theory for optimal investments under model uncertainty. Stat. Decis. 23(3), 199–217 (2005). MR2236457. https://doi.org/10.1524/stnd.2005.23.3.199
[22] 
Schmeidler, D.: Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica, 571–587 (1989). https://doi.org/10.2307/1911053
[23] 
Shevchenko, G.M.: Arbitrage in a discrete-time financial risk model with a proportional tax on the portfolio size. Theory Probab. Math. Stat. 81, 177–186 (2010). MR2667318. https://doi.org/10.1090/S0094-9000-2011-00818-6
[24] 
Sion, M.: On general minimax theorems. Pac. J. Math. 8(1), 171–176 (1958) MR0097026
[25] 
Yaari, M.E.: The dual theory of choice under risk. Econometrica, 95–115 (1987). MR0875518. https://doi.org/10.2307/1911158
Exit Reading PDF XML


Table of contents
  • 1 Introduction
  • 2 Minimax identity for nonconcave utility functions in complete market model
  • 3 Minimax identity for constrained case of random endowments
  • A Auxiliary statements
  • Acknowledgement
  • References

Export citation

Copy and paste formatted citation
Placeholder

Download citation in file


Share


RSS

MSTA

MSTA

  • Online ISSN: 2351-6054
  • Print ISSN: 2351-6046
  • Copyright © 2018 VTeX

About

  • About journal
  • Indexed in
  • Editors-in-Chief

For contributors

  • Submit
  • OA Policy
  • Become a Peer-reviewer

Contact us

  • ejournals-vmsta@vtex.lt
  • Mokslininkų 2A
  • LT-08412 Vilnius
  • Lithuania
Powered by PubliMill  •  Privacy policy